Wednesday, May 21, 2008

Marxalot

Turn on the news, it looks like a movie
It just makes me want to sing Louie Louie


From looking at my stats, I see what the vast majority of LI’s readership wants: naked pictures of Lady Bitch Ray. Unfortunately, she hasn’t mailed me any lately. So I will revert to a few jottings about a subject so sexy and hot that surely, aficionados of LBR’s perfect derriere will not be totally unhappy. I’m speaking, of course, about Marx and the German Ideology.

Ho ho.

Northanger, at a certain late point in the comment stream on Phantoms of Ideology, asked me what it was that I found particularly stunning about Amie’s discussion of ideology in Marx. What I found stunning about it was that Amie took Marx’s notion apart, and showed how it worked and didn’t work. This is in the best tradition of what Victor Skhlovsky, the Russian critique, called “estrangement” – by examining a thing as a composite rather than as a immediate whole, one gains a certain intellectual and moral mastery over a seemingly opaque totality. In his great essay about the estrangement in Wooden Eyes, Carlo Ginzberg relates the technique to folk riddles and the Stoic moral training found in Marcus Aurelius. “First of all, we must pause and take stock. That which is dear to us must be broken down into its component parts.” This, one of the pre-eminent intellectual urges inherited by the early modern moralists from the revival of the Stoics (see La Bruyere’s passage about going into the kitchens of the rich and observing each (disgusting) stage in the preparation of their delicacies) flows into the ideologues proper of the Napoleonic era, and then into Marx’s own use of “ideology” in The German Ideology. As Amie points out, if we go back into the kitchen and see when and how Marx composed a book in 1846 that did not get published until 1932, we will experience a certain lessening of our sense of, well, our grasp on the text. That lessened grasp is important, especially in light of the fact that there is a central Marxist tradition that believe it “owns” the text. Chabert, whose reduction of Marx's use of ideology as three memorizable uses, seems to assume something opposite: we can simply pluck out the “concepts” that constitute the meaning of Marx's text and arrange them synchronically, like bulleted items in a power point presentation.

That is the traditional way of interpreting Marx.

Well, I wrote at mindboggling length in the comments about this in response to Chabert. However, I’d like to pull away from the duel and scratch out a few notes about the German Ideology that I will no doubt later use in my happiness book.

Anyone who tries to read the entirety of the German Ideology quickly finds that it is the gaudiest, oddest text in Marx’s canon. It goes on forever, contains gigantic, brilliant guesses and then ties them to a pitifully provincial controversy. It is crucial to remember that this text is written long before Marx had anything like a model of capitalism. In this, it is a sort of unique document in science – not only does Marx lack empirical evidence for his claims, he even lacks a model to generate that evidence. And yet, he advances with an amazing confidence, in the process creating a radically new social science.

The title is, of course, meant seriously. This book is Marx’s spirited entry in the contest to pull Germany – a nation that doesn’t even exist – into the sphere of the vanguard European nations. There is no doubt in Marx’s mind that the industrial system invented in Europe is the future. Unlike, say, Gandhi, who confronted a similarly backward economy in India, Marx does not think the industrial system is evidence of Western ‘vice’. His tone is all the more sarcastic as he is waging this polemic against a handful of former theology students who are rich in a sophisticated philosophical vocabulary, but poor in their sense of reality. If Germany does not become part of civilization, its destiny will be decided on the outside, without it. This intuition is perfectly correct – Marx doesn’t have any sympathy for concerns about Kultur, which, to him, is just the last mumblings of the feudal aristocracy. Marx is, to use an anachronistic vocabulary, completely Eurocentric. The European idea is not that Europe is mystically superior, but that the industrial system developed in Europe is globally applicable. This is the essence of the Western idea. Without it, there would be no universal working class for Marxism to work with. Marx wholeheartedly supported 'civilization'. In political terms, this meant support for the advances of bourgeois liberal democracy, which he vociferously supported in 1848. And good for him. But it also meant that the global phenomenon of the 19th and 20th century – the triumph of the West - was advanced both by Marxism and capitalism. Left and Right (those incredibly provincial terms, referencing a temporary assembly in Paris and projecting it onto the global conceptual space as if were a god given filter) fundamentally agree on their vision of the world – that is, on the necessity of the industrial system, which is the central term defining civilization. No communist party in the 20th century - neither Bose's in Bengal, Ho Chi Minh's in Hanoi, or Castro's in Havana - disagree with that. (Hmm, well, no, there are two exceptions - the Khmer Rouge and Mao, which, in their monstrosity, speak for themselves.) Whereever these two forces went, they left behind factories. Whether the management of that industrial system was market based or based on the enfranchised power of the laborer was the question, but the industrial system was never questioned.

In making his case against the German ideology, Marx begins the book with his biggest and most fruitful guess. Taking the conjectural history of progress that characterized the Edinburgh enlightenment and the French ideologues, i.e. folks like Smith, Ferguson and Condorcet, Marx reorganizes it under the sign of a brilliant insight: instead of freedom or the arts and sciences being the driver of progress, Marx redefines the historical dynamic in terms of systems of production. At a stroke, Marx gives us a sociology that does not appeal to some final, qualitative absolute.

This was brilliant. It was revolutionary. And it was also without any support from either a model or empirical data. At this point, Marx’s economic model is solely that created by the bourgeois economists.

Along with this insight, Marx makes a second move, one as important as the first. He discusses systems of production in terms of labor, and – at least partially – founds a social ontology that frees labor from both feudal hierarchical thought and the ‘ideologues” dualism. Consciousness is being. All production uses both thought and bodily power. Social being is founded on the life processes. This is an exciting moment in Marx. He has given himself the tools to discuss labor outside of the idealist model of his theological opponents, but he has provided grounds for discarding the dualism between ideas and matter. At this point, one would think he would discard all –isms.

Alas, he doesn’t. This is where the polemical nature of the book, which makes it fun to read, exacts its price from Marx’s theory. To admit that ideas are part of the life process would be, strategically, giving a hostage to fortune – and Marx is a take no prisoners kind of guy. Thus, he proclaims himself, absurdly enough, a materialist, and distorts his discovery to produce a whacky idea of ideas as these things that sort of float, effeminately, in the ether, while labor goes on, ever material. The hammerer and the hammer are one.

This theme muddies Marx’s clarity. It is also the first appearance of what becomes a truly vicious habit in Marxism, and on the left, where everything gets dubbed “material”. Materialism is the Semper Fi of Marxism, a meaningless slogan to excuse mean and disgusting actions. Moreover, by embracing a dualism he has just exploded, Marx burdens himself with an unnecessarily idealistic conception of ideas. He misses their materiality.

This confusion is compounded in Marx’s first definition of ideology. You can tell Marx is going backwards when he uses a metaphor that naturalizes a cultural phenomenon:

“The fact is thus this: particular [bestimmte] individuals who are productively active in particular ways, enter into particular social and political relationships. Empirical observation must in every individual case point to the empirical coordination of a social and political division with that of production and without any mystification and speculation. Social division and the state issue constantly out of the life process of particular individuals; but these individuals may not appear as they exist in their own or in other’s thought, but as they really are, meaning, as they operate, materially produce, thus as they are active under specific material limits, presuppositions and conditions, independent of their will.

The production of ideas, thoughts of the consciousness is firstly immediately imbricated in the material activity and the material intercourse of men, languages of real life. The thoughts, thinking, the spiritual intercourse of men appear here still as the direct overflow of their material relations. [Das Vorstellen, Denken, der geistige Verkehr der Menschen erscheinen hier noch als direkter Ausfluß ihres materiellen Verhaltens] The same thing goes for the spiritual production, as they are represented in the language of politics, of laws, of morals, of religion, metaphysics, etc., of a people. People are the producers of their thoughts, ideas, but real working people, as they are conditioned through a particular development of their productive forces and of the corresponding intercourse up to its broadest formation. Consciousness can never be something other than conscious being, and the being of men is their real process of living. If in the collective ideology of people, men and their relations appear, as in a camera obscura, standing on its head, so, too, this phenomenon is attributable to their historical living process, as the inversion of the object on the retina is to their immediate physical ones.”

Magnificent rhetoric, but one that puts Marx himself, as the writer of the German Ideology, in the uncomfortable position of writing from a practically supernatural viewpoint – after all, if the collective ideology of a people is as ingrained as the image is on the retina, one can only overcome that ideology by operating, in a metaphoric way, supernaturally. Such exaggeration is normal to Marx when he polemicizes – polemic operates both to get his best ideas on paper and then to contour them to the amazingly petty matters at hand. Thus, a quarrel in a backwards European state between journalists and junior academics has the result of dividing the whole world of human thought into the materialist or the idealist. Which leads Marx to soem fatally dismissive talk about ideas, as though they were somehow not material, as though they didn't arise and return to living processes, as though the brain were composed of ghost stuff.

Thus, it is this overabundance of the material that leads to those rather unfortunate passages in which Marx puts his ideological idea to work. I’ll quote from a passage that I’m not going to translate – I don’t have time! – but take from the often suspect International Press translation:

“The ideas of the ruling class are in every epoch the ruling ideas, i.e. the class which is the ruling material force of society, is at the same time its ruling intellectual force. The class which has the means of material production at its disposal, has control at the same time over the means of mental production, so that thereby, generally speaking, the ideas of those who lack the means of mental production are subject to it. The ruling ideas are nothing more than the ideal expression of the dominant material relationships, the dominant material relationships grasped as ideas; hence of the relationships which make the one class the ruling one, therefore, the ideas of its dominance. The individuals composing the ruling class possess among other things consciousness, and therefore think. Insofar, therefore, as they rule as a class and determine the extent and compass of an epoch, it is self-evident that they do this in its whole range, hence among other things rule also as thinkers, as producers of ideas, and regulate the production and distribution of the ideas of their age: thus their ideas are the ruling ideas of the epoch. For instance, in an age and in a country where royal power, aristocracy, and bourgeoisie are contending for mastery and where, therefore, mastery is shared, the doctrine of the separation of powers proves to be the dominant idea and is expressed as an “eternal law.”

Again, what magnificent rhetoric! And surely right in parts, in that the material of ideas in a social reality are taken from that social reality. And yet, it is a generalization that depends on a mystified notion of “intellectual force,” which makes no sense outside of the mechanism where ‘ideas’ occur. Thus, somehow we are supposed to think that the idea of separation of powers proves (how?) to be the dominant idea – really? – and is expressed as ‘eternal law’ – seriously begging the question of where this cultural value comes from. This kind of simple, unmediated ideological critique makes for a nice journalistic shorthand, but as a description of social reality, it, of course, sucks. The royal power, aristocracy and bourgeoisie are stripped of their historic specificity, here, the material means by which they actually existed in real life, and defined in the abstract terms of their interest in domination. Again, there is some truth to this, but these words mystify more than they explain, creating a tableau of ghostly forces struggling for ‘material’ and ever more material prizes – although, of course, after a certain level, the life process of the human being in the ruling class is tidily taken care of, if we take material literally. Power becomes, then, another “force”, another mystery. I like the way Derrida uses the term program for this kind of thing, which is preferable on every level – the idea in the head, the spoken word, the written text, they are all involved not in a mysterious expressive relationship to ‘dominant material relationships’ – matter being again the compulsive word – but are embedded in them, are on the same level as them. Court society wouldn’t exist without those ‘expressive’ relationships – in fact, no society would. Marx forgets his notion of living processes, here, he forgets that the brain is what thinks, and that throughout the career of a thought, it is never outside of its ‘material’ nexus.

This polemically obsessive turn to the material that, ironically, is copacetic with the most highly idealistic notion of thought, is part of the program that Marx has to revamp after 1848, per Amie. But the compulsive display of toughness, the superabundance of “materiality”, the misbegotten contempt for ideas, based on a misbegotten notion of their function and their social place, existed as part of one of the programs in Marx’s texts. And they were used, with various catastrophic results, in 20th century Marxism.

Which I’ll come back to, at some point, if I have time.

23 comments:

  1. Oops, in the version I had jotted down - and this is of some importance - I wanted to point out one contradiction that Marx falls into in his 1846 definition of ideology. In all production, in Marx, it is the workers who produce. It is not the capitalists. One would not say, for instance, that Andrew Carnegie made the steel produced by his company. It was produced by the company's employees. And to say that Carnegie's spirit was "reflected" in that steel would be laughed at as the grossest form of capitalist propaganda. Yet, when it comes to producing "ideas", suddenly this model is reversed. All the ideas in, say, a newspaper bought by Carnegie "reflect" Carnegie. Indeed, the political philosophy of Locke, or Hobbes, or Condorcet, "reflects" the dominant class. The intellectual worker, alone, has this primarily alienated relationship to his or her product.

    Again, this is the result of Marx's insistence that he is a "materialist".

    ReplyDelete
  2. in the version I had jotted down [of this post in my notebook]. This is what comes of haste, my fellow sluggards.

    ReplyDelete
  3. LI, I'm sure you know that the kitchen metaphor touches on "women", as the kitchen is supposedly a woman's "domain", which is worth pondering maybe, and where she sees and deals with "materiality", or where her materiality is limited to? Almost, as she still has to "produce" material inheritance, only to disappear when that has happened. A quaint idea? Just ask Britney.

    But these posts have also been fun in that they remind me of what it is to read and think and act and not be totally intimidated by the authoritarian voice. North says it quite well:
    WHEN THE FUCK DID GOD GIVE YOU THE RIGHT TO NAME EVERYTHING AND APPOINT YOURSELF THE SOLE SUBJECT?

    LI, there is a whole lot in your post that i would like to get to, but at the moment I don't quite know how to, it is almost as if each line of thought mucks up the previous one. Ah, but there is music etc
    http://www.youtube.com/watch?v=lW0rosozta8


    Amie

    ReplyDelete
  4. Nouvelle Vague!
    Marx would go out of his way, get in debt, to make sure his daughters were educated in music and could dance. I love Marx for that, for all those begging letters.

    ReplyDelete
  5. Caught the latest LBR flap? On an April 24 tv appearance she gave her hosts a little box purportedly containing secretions from her vagina. Here, although truncated in the very opening:

    http://www.youtube.com/watch?v=m2u_e9-mv6Y

    ReplyDelete
  6. What can I say? LBR is a brilliant provacateuse. And that she is introducing "pussy" into the vocabulary of late night tv is, well, it is an advance of some kind. But fuck it, basically she's having fun.

    ReplyDelete
  7. North, hope you didn't mind attributing the phrase I quoted from your comment to you. I do rather like the phrase and question, and so had to repeat it!

    LI, it seems to me that the voice of Jenny von Westphalen Marx should also be heard in all this. So here is Jenny writing to Marx in June of 1844:

    "Do not write too angrily and irritably. You know how much more effective your other writings have been. Write either factually and delicately or humorously and lightly. Please, dear heart, let the pen glide over the paper, and even if it drops and stumbles occasionally, and a sentence with it, your ideas stand like the grenadiers of the Old Guard, so honorable and firm, and like them they can say, elle meurt mais elle ne se rend pas. What does it matter if the uniform hangs loosely and is not laced so tightly? What is so very nice about the French soldiers is their free and easy appearance. When you think of our stilted Prussians, doesn't it make you shudder? Loosen the harness, undo the cravat, and raise the shako – let the participles run free and place the words as they themselves would like. An army like yours must not march too rigidly. And your troops are after all going into battle."
    (Jenny)

    The phrase elle meurt mais elle ne se rend pas is underlined.

    Amie

    ReplyDelete
  8. This particular provocation lead to a formal complaint from the representative of the Catholic church on the board of Southwest German Radio, which carries the show, to the board of West German Radio, which produces it.
    I'd say she's having the time of her life.
    the fact that in the course of the innterview she taked at some length about racism against Arab and Turkish women in Germany seems to passed without public comment.

    ReplyDelete
  9. "compulsive display of toughness" - or outraged and well-motivated response to some very brutal opponents?

    The record of the critique of ideology does begin with that analysis of the harsh law against the 'theft' of wood and its stacked enforcement.

    Before he's run out of the country just for editorializing.

    ReplyDelete
  10. "Chabert, whose reduction of Marx's use of ideology as three memorizable uses, seems to assume something opposite: we can simply pluck out the “concepts” that constitute the meaning of Marx's text and arrange them synchronically, like bulleted items in a power point presentation. "

    argh! that's what comes of "unpacking" on request!

    (At least though if you cooperate you get to sort of guide the relentless caricaturing.)

    ReplyDelete
  11. To the question posed by Roger: In all production, in Marx, it is the workers who produce. It is not the capitalists. One would not say, for instance, that Andrew Carnegie made the steel produced by his company. It was produced by the company's employees. And to say that Carnegie's spirit was "reflected" in that steel would be laughed at as the grossest form of capitalist propaganda. Yet, when it comes to producing "ideas", suddenly this model is reversed. All the ideas in, say, a newspaper bought by Carnegie "reflect" Carnegie. Indeed, the political philosophy of Locke, or Hobbes, or Condorcet, "reflects" the dominant class. The intellectual worker, alone, has this primarily alienated relationship to his or her product.

    Again, this is the result of Marx's insistence that he is a "materialist".


    It's not as though the ruling class produces nothing whatsoever--the production of ruling class ideology isn't an idealist sleight-of-hand because the proletariat have a monopoly on any production at all; rather the important thing is where in the social makeup that a particular site of production exists, no? Mandel writes (here):

    The immediate object of class struggle is economic and material. It is a struggle for the division of the social product between the direct producers (the productive, exploited class) and those who appropriate what Marx calls the social surplus product, the residuum of the social product once the producers and their offspring are fed (in the large sense of the word; i.e. the sum total of the consumer goods consumed by that class) and the initial stock of tools and raw materials is reproduced (including the restoration of the initial fertility of the soil). The ruling class functions as a ruling class essentially through the appropriation of the social surplus product. By getting possession of the social surplus product, it acquires the means to foster and maintain most of the superstructural activities mentioned above; and by doing so, it can largely determine their function - to maintain and reproduce the given social structure, the given mode of production - and their contents.

    ReplyDelete
  12. Ah, that mystifing rhetoric. Here we find no newspapers, no laws or lawyers or courts, no media, no folktales, no symbols (which cannot exist without matter), but "superstructure" and "appropriation." In fact, the assumptions - all idealistic, all involving a conflictless superstructure busily working away to maintain their given social structure - are simply never seen. As far back as the beginning of writing, you have - as you'd expect to have - conflicts in every sphere, mechanisms of selection (from the way censorship is state controlled to the forms for hiring in universities, to use two simple examples from Marx's time), all of which suggest that the idea of a social surplus product (again with the crazy idea that there's meat below, workers with no ideas, and ghosts above, intellectual forces with no meat) that, in fact, is just wordplay. There's nothing surplus about it. What, do you think humans normally grunt at each other? There is not a work crew in the world in which the surplus social product isn't pervasive.

    Again, the translation of Marx's materialism into an analysis of intellectual life always devolves into this incredible phantasmagoria of idealistic entities, with class becoming a notion so abstract it is hard to see where it is embedded at all.

    ReplyDelete
  13. Ah, Zack, I shouldn't have replied in such an exasperated tone. But that kind of writing does exasperate me. Its assumptions are so unhooked from any empirical data - like, where do journalists and writers and artists and scribes come from, what do their career trajectories look like, how does the law work, what is the point of the idea of a dominant class that seems to express itself by telepathy, etc - and it is so sedimented with classist assumptions - that I grow impatient hearing that stuff.

    ReplyDelete
  14. Well, in the Mandel piece I've quoted, when he refers to the "superstructural activities mentioned above," those activities are clear enough--"the state and the law (except in a classless society), ideology, religion, philosophy, the arts, morality, etc." (Presumably this encompasses newspapers, laws, lawyers, courts, media, folktales, and symbols.) It's a generalization, yes, but it's a necessary one unless you want every Marxist to go through a list whereby one never ever says "superstructure," but, "television shows, radio shows, websites, the penal code, the tax code, organized religions, the education system, etc., etc., ad nauseum." It's shorthand but it's not as though it's a mystery. To critique the generalization one can't simply name it as such, as though it's by necessity "vague idealism," and BANG, that's it. One has to find an example of an agreed-upon superstructural element that generally contradicts the use of the term.

    I agree that the "crazy idea that there's meat below, workers with no ideas, and ghosts above, intellectual forces with no meat" is a crazy idea. I'm just not seeing how it's Marx's idea. Where does he write that workers produce no thoughts, have no ideologies of their own, for instance? Does he ever come out and say that ruling class ideology, the dominant superstructure, is monolithic and immaterial? I would think that if one's going to critize Marx here it's rather for running the risk of mere truisms here--that is, the minority set of people in power, by means of legislative, judicial, educational, and information dissemination, cultivate policies, regulations, worldviews, and value systems that benefit them overall and help keep them in place. This doesn't mean there's no disagreement, no agency, no materiality at all among factions and between individuals of the ruling class (and it doesn't mean there isn't a gradient, even a porosity, as to how deeply one is even "in" the ruling class)--look at the mass media, plenty of "debate" on issues X,Y, and Z. It's the framing of this debate, however, that is set by a wealthy elite, the owners of the media corporations and their advertisers and funders (same things?)--it produces its own truisms like "economic growth is good," which is the underlying assumption no matter which two policy wanks you have debating on MSNBC.

    ReplyDelete
  15. North, you are once again on one of your amazing rolls. Thanks for your above comment, and I'm still all thinking about your comment in "The Phantom of Ideology" post about Melville and 1848, which somehow got lost in all the "shuffle". I haven't quite figured a way to adequately respond in comment threads, seem to get all sidetracked and such and, as with that comment of yours. Or with LI's comments re kitchens. Have you seen Renoir's La Règle du jeu? It is from 1939 and is all about a world and a society that is passing away and one yet to come. (Or to put it in "marxist" terms, about "transition"). Anyway, most of the movie takes place in this chateau in the French countryside and Renoir knew well enough to make the kitchen a part of it and indeed long sequences of the film are devoted to what happens "underneath" the mansion, in the kitchen. Ah, see here I am rambling on a tangent!

    Zack, to your question - "Where does he [Marx] write that workers produce no thoughts, have no ideologies of their own, for instance?" He does so in the German Ideology, where the proletariat is completely outside "ideology".

    Amie

    ReplyDelete
  16. Well, Zach, I just replied to you, and this dumb comment thing ate my reply. So sad! Such great stuff! I'm cryin'!

    Anyway, to remember what I wrote: to introduce structure and superstructure is just to translate the old dualism of idea and matter into other terms. It doesn't do away with it, but, again, mystifies Mental production, as though it were some special instance. That the mental and material production are so bound to each other that, on the fundamental level, abstract them one from the other distorts them, is where I am coming from, and what I pick up on in Marx. We are, after all, organisms with brains. When Marx speaks of mental production as expressing the material relations in a society, that is true, just as it is true that glassware, or nails, or lumber express the material relations in a society. The difference with mental production is that the barrier to entry is very low, close to zero. The merest infant can enter into the intellectual product circuit.

    Marx hesitates in the German Ideology between certain choices, and - as I say - I read him as coming to the edge of doing away with dualism of a certain type - which, I should say, is not plumping for monism. I wrote that I believe Marx surrenders to a polemical impulse when he retreats and puts ideas in a secondary position in the production process, things that are derivative of the conditions of labor - as if labor weren't through and through about instruction, routine, daydream, rhythm, and all the cognitive equipment we have. It is at this point that one longs for Engels more ethnological touch. The impulse to make the separation and to talk about ideas and "intellectual force" comes from fighting the "idealists". But I think the Derridian notion that there is a program, here, an enchainment that leads from materialism to the familiar hierarchy of structure/superstructure, matter/thought, the usual logocentrism m.o., has a lot to recommend it.

    ReplyDelete
  17. Hm. I don't quite see how the "old dualism" is being reproduced, how Marx is abstracting superstructure into Idea. I think I'm beginning to grasp your points but as of yet they're not matching up to what I think Marx is fairly clearly saying.

    Unfortunately I have to cut off my meager contributions to the debate now, and won't be back until Wednesday (if anything is still going on). I'll take another look at GI in the meantime and ponder some more. Thanks for hosting.

    ReplyDelete
  18. roger. glass & eyeballs: The Torah is full of holy fire; it was written with a black fire upon a white fire... Poor ignorant man, you want to find out God's ways; explain first the phenomenon of your own eye; it consists of white and black, and according to all reason the white should supply light, but in reality the little spot in the center of your eye is the lens to give you sight... Man's eyes have white and black in them; but the power of sight, the lens supplying light, is the black.

    AO 192 = PHYSICAL LIGHT ALWAYS RECEIVES FROM SPIRITUAL LIGHT (p123, fifth sentence; next 3 sentences: Thus, there are four different types of fire, and these are the ones that God showed to Moses. These are red fire, yellow fire, white fire, and black fire. [19. Cf. BaMidbar Rabbah 12:8, Zohar 2:241a.] {oh great! always wondered how Ham got black}) = \, ^{249}_{98}\MATHRM{CF} + \, ^{18}_{8}\MATHRM{O} \, \TO\ \, ^{263}_{106}\MATHRM{SG} + 4\, ^{1}_{0}\MATHRM{N} (AO-36 SEABORGIUM) = 7º SAGITTARIUS (247): CUPID KNOCKING AT THE DOOR OF A HUMAN HEART = FOR IT IS WRITTEN THAT A SON OF ARABIA WOULD AWAKEN A FEARSOME EAGLE = INCANTATORY MAGIC OF ONOMASTICS AND APPELLATIONS CONTRÔLÉES (AO-48 SPECTERS OF MARX) = OBJECTS ARE TRANSFORMED INTO SUBJECTS AND SUBJECTS ARE TURNED INTO OBJECTS (AO-50 REIFICATION) = PREMISED IN THE FOLLOWING MATERIALIST CONCEPTION (AO-77 HISTORICAL MATERIALISM) = REQUIRING EACH OTHER TO COMPLETE THEIR DEVELOPMENT (AO-78 THE GERMAN IDEOLOGY) = STIRRED FOR A BIRD,-THE ACHIEVE OF; THE MASTERY OF THE THING! ({8}; AO-59 THE WINDHOVER).

    ReplyDelete
  19. Bamidbar means "in the wilderness" (Numbers 1:1 And the LORD spoke unto Moses in the wilderness of Sinai, in the tent of meeting, on the first day of the second month, in the second year after they were come out of the land of Egypt); referenced by RFK (on the cover of this month's Vanity Fair): In 1824, when Thomas Hart Benton was urging in Congress the development of Iowa and other western territories, he was opposed by Daniel Webster, the Senator from Massachusetts. "What," asked Webster, "what do we want with this vast and worthless area? This region of savages and wild beasts. Of deserts of shifting sands and of whirlwinds. Of dust, and of cactus and of prairie dogs. To what use," he said, "could we ever hope to put these great deserts? I will never vote for one-cent from the public treasury, to place the west one inch closer to Boston, than it is now." &c.

    ReplyDelete
  20. LCC - I like that quote of Derrida's. Of course, I'm making the same point in a different vocabulary - the idea of this superstructure of laws erected above the silent working of the system of production is not only historically untrue, inverts the historical process (as Polanyi puts it, the state designed capitalism) but blinds the social analyst to one of the crucial aspects of the worldwide spread of the industrial system. Even Polanyi is simply playing with the same binaries. This hierachical structure, with reference to which ideology, in Marx's first sense, is defined, is in contradiction with Marx's own notion of labor as, indeed, a affair that mixes matter and idea, and the reader must ask: what motivates the contradiction? Derrida's answer, ontology, is pretty good. The very idea that one is forced to hypothesize some superstructure that acts above the silent structures of the social whole, reducing law entirely to ideology - as if law wasn't intrinsic to the global change in property relations without which capitalism couldn't have arisen - comes out of the program of materialism, out of defending that metaphysical move. In the process, Marx reproduces the binaries of the classical and neo-classical economist. Derrida captures the problem in Marx here, very precisely:

    "But, on the other hand, even as he remains one of the first thinkers of technics, or even, by far and from afar, of the tele-technology that it will always have been, from near or from far, Marx continues to want to ground his critique or his exorcism of the spectral simulacrum in an ontology."

    This is a very good diagnosis. Marx's 'ideology', here, is complicit with the ideology of capitalism - indeed, both tend, at this point, to embed the social completely in the economic. The same kind of ideological gesture, the same "forgetting" of the law, is carried out by the neo-classicals. You can see this most clearly in Hayek's Road to Serfdom, for instance. There, too, the state is treated as a superstructure, something that should not interfere with the economy, as if the law were some ideological afterthought to the autonomous genesis of the capitalist system of production. In this way, the state's use of the law, and in fact the entire way the law and conventions operate in society, are mystified. Marx, as I've emphasized, is not a monolithic writer, but whenever he tends towards the 'materialist" ontology, he loses his grasp on how systems of production work. He injects an old hierarchy, which puts the slave, the thoughtless laborer, under the master, the lawgiver - which is not overturned by inversing these relations, but by seeing that the slave is not a thoughtless laborer, and that law and conventions are not totally under the control of the master - that in fact there is not one master.

    ReplyDelete
  21. "I'm making the same point in a different vocabulary - the idea of this superstructure of laws erected above the silent working of the system of production "

    but roger, you are merely pretending you think "The totality of these [social] relations of production..." means "a silent working of a system of production"; its too extreme a misquote! you might as well say "the totality of social relations" means "a red whale with white polka dots". How are you going to convince people that human social relations are "silent" and mindless? Everybody knows they aren't!

    ReplyDelete
  22. and if you disagreed with the notion - which is derrida's of course - that "the silent working of system of production" conditions human consciousness and social relations, then it remains to be explained how you can accept that the telecom technology (the silent working of system of production) can so completely determine consciousness and social relations, even abolishing independent, living consciousness altogether, as derrida asserts.

    ReplyDelete
  23. ""But, on the other hand, even as he remains one of the first thinkers of technics, or even, by far and from afar, of the tele-technology that it will always have been, from near or from far, Marx continues to want to ground his critique or his exorcism of the spectral simulacrum in an ontology."


    it says: Marx was not enough of a technological determinist.

    ReplyDelete